HoareAsLogicHoare Logic as a Logic

The presentation of Hoare logic in chapter Hoare could be described as "model-theoretic": the proof rules for each of the constructors were presented as theorems about the evaluation behavior of programs, and proofs of program correctness (validity of Hoare triples) were constructed by combining these theorems directly in Coq.
Another way of presenting Hoare logic is to define a completely separate proof system — a set of axioms and inference rules that talk about commands, Hoare triples, etc. — and then say that a proof of a Hoare triple is a valid derivation in that logic. We can do this by giving an inductive definition of valid derivations in this new logic.
Before reading this chapter, you'll want to read the ProofObjects chapter in Logical Foundations (Software Foundations, volume 1).

Definitions


Inductive hoare_proof : AssertioncomAssertionType :=
  | H_Skip : P,
      hoare_proof P (SKIP) P
  | H_Asgn : Q V a,
      hoare_proof (Q [V > a]) (V ::= a) Q
  | H_Seq : P c Q d R,
      hoare_proof P c Qhoare_proof Q d Rhoare_proof P (c;;d) R
  | H_If : P Q b c1 c2,
    hoare_proof (fun stP stbassn b st) c1 Q
    hoare_proof (fun stP st ∧ ~(bassn b st)) c2 Q
    hoare_proof P (TEST b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) Q
  | H_While : P b c,
    hoare_proof (fun stP stbassn b st) c P
    hoare_proof P (WHILE b DO c END) (fun stP st ∧ ¬(bassn b st))
  | H_Consequence : (P Q P' Q' : Assertion) c,
    hoare_proof P' c Q'
    (st, P stP' st) →
    (st, Q' stQ st) →
    hoare_proof P c Q.
We don't need to include axioms corresponding to hoare_consequence_pre or hoare_consequence_post, because these can be proven easily from H_Consequence.
Lemma H_Consequence_pre : (P Q P': Assertion) c,
    hoare_proof P' c Q
    (st, P stP' st) →
    hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
  intros. eapply H_Consequence.
    apply X. apply H. intros. apply H0. Qed.

Lemma H_Consequence_post : (P Q Q' : Assertion) c,
    hoare_proof P c Q'
    (st, Q' stQ st) →
    hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
  intros. eapply H_Consequence.
    apply X. intros. apply H0. apply H. Qed.
As an example, let's construct a proof object representing a derivation for the hoare triple
      {{(X=3) [X > X + 2] [X > X + 1]}}
      X::=X+1 ;; X::=X+2
      {{X=3}}.
We can use Coq's tactics to help us construct the proof object.
Example sample_proof :
  hoare_proof
    ((fun st:statest X = 3) [X > X + 2] [X > X + 1])
    (X ::= X + 1;; X ::= X + 2)
    (fun st:statest X = 3).
Proof.
  eapply H_Seq; apply H_Asgn.
Qed.

Print sample_proof.
(*
====>
  H_Seq
  (((fun st : state => st X = 3) X > X + 2X > X + 1)
  (X ::= X + 1)
  ((fun st : state => st X = 3) X > X + 2)
  (X ::= X + 2)
  (fun st : state => st X = 3)
  (H_Asgn
     ((fun st : state => st X = 3) X > X + 2)
     X (X + 1))
  (H_Asgn
     (fun st : state => st X = 3)
     X (X + 2))
*)

Properties

Exercise: 2 stars, standard (hoare_proof_sound)

Prove that derivations constructed with hoare_proof correspond to valid Hoare triples. In other words, hoare_proof derivations are sound. Hint: We already proved the soundness of each individual proof rule in Hoare as theorems hoare_skip, hoare_asgn, etc.; leverage those proofs.
Theorem hoare_proof_sound : P c Q,
  hoare_proof P c Q{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
We can also use Coq's reasoning facilities to prove metatheorems about Hoare Logic. For example, here are the analogues of two theorems we saw in chapter Hoare — this time expressed in terms of the syntax of Hoare Logic derivations (provability) rather than directly in terms of the semantics of Hoare triples.
The first one says that, for every P and c, the assertion {{P}} c {{True}} is provable in Hoare Logic. Note that the proof is more complex than the semantic proof in Hoare: we actually need to perform an induction over the structure of the command c.
Theorem H_Post_True_deriv:
  c P, hoare_proof P c (fun _True).
Proof.
  intro c.
  induction c; intro P.
  - (* SKIP *)
    eapply H_Consequence.
    apply H_Skip.
    intros. apply H.
    (* Proof of True *)
    intros. apply I.
  - (* ::= *)
    eapply H_Consequence_pre.
    apply H_Asgn.
    intros. apply I.
  - (* ;; *)
    eapply H_Consequence_pre.
    eapply H_Seq.
    apply (IHc1 (fun _True)).
    apply IHc2.
    intros. apply I.
  - (* TEST *)
    apply H_Consequence_pre with (fun _True).
    apply H_If.
    apply IHc1.
    apply IHc2.
    intros. apply I.
  - (* WHILE *)
    eapply H_Consequence.
    eapply H_While.
    eapply IHc.
    intros; apply I.
    intros; apply I.
Qed.
Similarly, we can show that {{False}} c {{Q}} is provable for any c and Q.
Lemma False_and_P_imp: P Q,
  FalsePQ.
Proof.
  intros P Q [CONTRA HP].
  destruct CONTRA.
Qed.

Tactic Notation "pre_false_helper" constr(CONSTR) :=
  eapply H_Consequence_pre;
    [eapply CONSTR | intros ? CONTRA; destruct CONTRA].

Theorem H_Pre_False_deriv:
  c Q, hoare_proof (fun _False) c Q.
Proof.
  intros c.
  induction c; intro Q.
  - (* SKIP *) pre_false_helper H_Skip.
  - (* ::= *) pre_false_helper H_Asgn.
  - (* ;; *) pre_false_helper H_Seq. apply IHc1. apply IHc2.
  - (* TEST *)
    apply H_If; eapply H_Consequence_pre.
    apply IHc1. intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
    apply IHc2. intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
  - (* WHILE *)
    eapply H_Consequence_post.
    eapply H_While.
    eapply H_Consequence_pre.
      apply IHc.
      intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
    intro. simpl. eapply False_and_P_imp.
Qed.
As a last step, we can show that the set of hoare_proof axioms is sufficient to prove any true fact about (partial) correctness. More precisely, any semantic Hoare triple that we can prove can also be proved from these axioms. Such a set of axioms is said to be relatively complete. That is, the axioms are complete relative to what we can prove in the underlying assertion language. If there are gaps in what can be proved in that language, then we blame it, not the Hoare logic axioms.
Our proof is inspired by this one:
  http://www.ps.uni-saarland.de/courses/sem-ws11/script/Hoare.html
To carry out the proof, we need to invent some intermediate assertions using a technical device known as weakest preconditions (which are also discussed in Hoare2). Given a command c and a desired postcondition assertion Q, the weakest precondition wp c Q is an assertion P such that {{P}} c {{Q}} holds, and moreover, for any other assertion P', if {{P'}} c {{Q}} holds then P' P. We can more directly define this as follows:
Definition wp (c:com) (Q:Assertion) : Assertion :=
  fun ss', s =[ c ]⇒ s'Q s'.
To get accustomed to this definition of wp, prove the next two simple theorems.

Exercise: 1 star, standard (wp_is_precondition)


Theorem wp_is_precondition : c Q,
  {{wp c Q}} c {{Q}}.
Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 1 star, standard (wp_is_weakest)


Theorem wp_is_weakest : c Q P',
   {{P'}} c {{Q}} → st, P' stwp c Q st.
Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard (wp_invariant)

Prove that for any Q, assertion wp (WHILE b DO c END) Q is an invariant of WHILE b DO c END.
Lemma wp_invariant : b c Inv Q,
    Inv = wp (WHILE b DO c END) Q
    → {{ fun stInv stbassn b st }} c {{ Inv }}.
Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
The following utility lemma will be useful in the next exercise.
Lemma bassn_eval_false : b st, ¬bassn b stbeval st b = false.
Proof.
  intros b st H. unfold bassn in H. destruct (beval st b).
    exfalso. apply H. reflexivity.
    reflexivity.
Qed.

Exercise: 4 stars, standard (hoare_proof_complete)

Complete the proof of the theorem. Hint for the WHILE case: you need to invent a loop invariant.
Theorem hoare_proof_complete: P c Q,
  {{P}} c {{Q}} → hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
  intros P c. generalize dependent P.
  induction c; intros P Q HT.
  - (* SKIP *)
    eapply H_Consequence.
     eapply H_Skip.
      intros. eassumption.
      intro st. apply HT. apply E_Skip.
  - (* ::= *)
    eapply H_Consequence.
      eapply H_Asgn.
      intro st. apply HT. constructor. reflexivity.
      intros; assumption.
  - (* ;; *)
    apply H_Seq with (wp c2 Q).
     eapply IHc1.
       intros st st' E1 H. unfold wp. intros st'' E2.
         eapply HT. econstructor; eassumption. assumption.
     eapply IHc2. intros st st' E1 H. apply H; assumption.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Finally, we might hope that our axiomatic Hoare logic is decidable; that is, that there is an (terminating) algorithm (a decision procedure) that can determine whether or not a given Hoare triple is valid (derivable). But such a decision procedure cannot exist!
Consider the triple {{True}} c {{False}}. This triple is valid if and only if c is non-terminating. So any algorithm that could determine validity of arbitrary triples could solve the Halting Problem.
Similarly, the triple {{True}} SKIP {{P}} is valid if and only if s, P s is valid, where P is an arbitrary assertion of Coq's logic. But it is known that there can be no decision procedure for this logic.
Overall, this axiomatic style of presentation gives a clearer picture of what it means to "give a proof in Hoare logic." However, it is not entirely satisfactory from the point of view of writing down such proofs in practice: it is quite verbose. The section of chapter Hoare2 on formalizing decorated programs shows how we can do even better.